by ohthatpatrick Mon Apr 01, 2013 7:08 pm
LSAT rarely goes for TOTALLY irrelevant premises. (When we read an argument with two people talking, the 2nd person often objects to the 1st person but supplies an irrelevant reason)
But if you're reading one author's paragraph, try to figure out what the INTENDED match was.
Sometimes it helps to reverse-engineer the argument from the conclusion.
Conc: Mary would make a good Drackedary player
(What do I know about Mary? What do I know about "good Drackedary player"?)
Prem: Good at Drackedary --> skilled with their hands
Prem: Mary is a competent watchmaker.
Since we know the conclusion wants to fuse 'Mary' with 'Good at Drackedary', it must be assuming that "skill with hands" is a match for "competent watchmaker".
I'll admit, I was a little surprised by the outside knowledge LSAT demands for us to follow this assumption easily, but we can otherwise get it structurally.
Making watches involves careful manipulations of tiny little watch parts, so I guess it's natural to think that watchmakers might be skilled with their hands (still an assumption we would have to explicitly hear to logically prove the argument, but LSAT expects us to get that the author is assuming that connection).
So let's add in the assumption
"competent watchmakers are skilled with their hands".
What's wrong with this argument
Prem: Good at Drackedary --> skilled with hands
Prem: Mary --> competent watchmaker --> skilled with hands
Conc: Thus Mary would be good at Drackedary.
That was backwards logic!
We know Mary is skilled with her hands, but that doesn't guarantee us that she'd be good at drackedary. We can't read that first conditional in reverse.
If you didn't pick up on the fact that the first sentence was a conditional, take a look again and see what wording tells us it is.
"invariably" is strong enough to be conditional.
So there are really two flaws in the argument:
assuming 'skilled w/ hands' follows from 'competent watchmaker'
and
reading a conditional rule backwards
We should expect to see both those flaws in the correct answer.
(A) This is airtight logic. It is not flawed, so we can move on.
Daryl --> in Daryl's family --> have long legs --> make good runner.
(B) This looks promising. We have a conditional. We have a language shift between 'write for a living' and 'published novelist for many years'. Let's check whether we have backwards logic.
Write for living --> enjoy reading
Julie = published novelist
If we assume that published novelist -> write for living, then we get
Julie -> published nov. -> write for living -> enjoy reading
So that was close, but there was no reversed logic.
(C) Looks promising. We have a conditional and a language shift.
Race car driver --> Good reflexes
Chris = table tennis player
If we assume that table tennis player -> good reflexes, then we get
Chris --> table tennis player --> good reflexes
In order to infer that Chris would be a good race car driver, we have to read the original conditional backwards. We have our winner!
(D) The first sentence is NOT conditional, using the word "often", so we don't need to bother reading any further.
(E) We have a conditional and a language shift.
Good skier --> learn to ice skate eventually
Erica = world-class skier
If we assume that world-class skier -> good skier (and why wouldn't we), we get
Erica -> world-class skier -> good skier -> learn to skate eventually
Does (E)'s conclusion read the original conditional backwards? No, it just changes the final idea from "learning eventually" to "learning quickly". Not the same as the original.
Hope this helps.